Communications Question

Description

( i am a single black female over 55) Identify and explain a relationship that you have been involved in which unconditional positive regard was upheld. What made this possible? Difficult?

Don't use plagiarized sources. Get Your Custom Assignment on
Communications Question
From as Little as $13/Page

Unformatted Attachment Preview

Journal of Moral Education, Vol. 33, No. 2, June 2004
Caring for the ethical ideal:
Nel Noddings on moral education
Roger Bergman*
Creighton University, USA
Nel Noddings is arguably one of the premier philosophers of moral education in the Englishspeaking world today. Although she is outside the mainstream theory, research, and practice
traditions of cognitive-developmentalism (the Kohlberg legacy) and of character education (which
is in public ascendancy), her body of work is unrivalled for originality of insight, comprehensiveness and coherence. Whilst Carol Gilligan’s In a different voice (1982) introduced the ethic of
caring into academic and public discourse, it is Noddings ‘who has done most to outline a specific
feminist position on moral education’ (McClellan, 1999, p. 104), and whose influence extends to
educational practice. This essay explicates Noddings’s vision in sufficient depth to make the
foregoing claims credible. Thematic focus is given to her attention to the ethical self or ethical
ideal. The paper also examines Noddings’s perspective on character education and the need to
incorporate a morality of evil into any serious educational philosophy or practice. It is less a
critical appraisal of that vision and perspective than an invitation to others to more fully engage
with Noddings’s writings.1
Introduction
As we build an ethic on caring and as we examine education under its guidance, we
shall see that the greatest obligation of educators, inside and outside formal schooling,
is to nurture the ethical ideals of those with whom they come in contact. (Noddings,
1984a, p. 49)
So says Nel Noddings in her first and seminal book, Caring: a feminine approach to
ethics and moral education, published in 1984. This theme of caring for our children’s
and students’ ethical ideals is fundamental to Noddings’s perspective throughout the
six books she has authored which discuss moral education and related topics. As she
writes in a recent volume, one of two published in 2002, Starting at home: caring and
social policy:
We put great emphasis on moral interdependence—our shared responsibility for the
moral strength or weakness of each member of our society. In ‘educating the [caring]
*Justice & Peace Studies Program, Creighton University, Omaha NE 68178, USA. Email:
[email protected]
ISSN 0305-7240 print; ISSN 1465-3877 online/04/020149-14
© 2004 Journal of Moral Education Ltd
DOI: 10.1080/0305724042000215203
150
R. Bergman
response,’ caring parents and teachers provide the conditions in which it is possible and
attractive for children to respond as carers to others. We show them how to care.
Children educated in this way gradually build an ethical ideal, a dependable caring self.
A society composed of people capable of caring—people who habitually draw on a
well-established ideal—will move toward social policies consonant with an ethic of care.
(Noddings, 2002a, p. 223)
To understand what Noddings means by this theme, I entertain three basic
questions: What is Noddings’s vision of the moral life? How do moral obligation and
motivation arise? How can education contribute to the moral life of students?
What is Noddings’s vision of the moral life?
Noddings’s probing analysis of the phenomenon of human caring is perhaps her
single most significant contribution to our understanding of the moral life. She
devotes three chapters to it in her first book, and recapitulates her basic themes in
a chapter each in The challenge to care in schools, published in 1992, and Starting at
home, published a decade later. One might say, however, that all of her work under
consideration in this essay explicates the meaning of human caring, in parent-child
and teacher-student relationships, in educational philosophy and practice and even
in the broader area of social policy.
The original condition in the language of the mother
The need to be cared for is a human universal. We are born absolutely dependent
on the caring of others. If our life is to be preserved, if we are to grow, if we are to
arrive at some level of acceptability in our culture and community (Noddings, 1992,
p. 45), we must be cared for constantly from the moment of our squalling debut in
the world. This dependency is, for Noddings, the ‘original condition’ (2002a,
p. 121), which I suspect she means us to hear as a corrective or complement to John
Rawls’s (1971) famously abstract and impersonal ‘original position’ behind a ‘veil of
ignorance’. As she writes in the Introduction to Caring:
One might say that ethics has been discussed largely in the language of the father: in
principles and propositions, in terms such as justification, fairness, justice. The
mother’s voice has been silent. Human caring and the memory of caring and being
cared for, which I shall argue form the foundation of ethical response, have not received
attention except as outcomes of ethical behavior. (Noddings, 1984a, p. 1)
If we are lucky, we will have ‘the memory of caring and being cared for’ by at least
one adult who has herself learned how to care by having been cared for. If we are
lucky, someone will have been ‘crazy about that kid!’ in Urie Bronfenbrenner’s
phrase, which Noddings fondly quotes in three of her books (1984a, p. 61; 1995;
p. 71; 2002a, p. 25). This kind of spontaneous caring for those we love, while in a
very real way learned, Noddings calls ‘natural caring’. The mother-child relationship, when the mother is a competent carer, is the key to understanding the moral
lives and obligations not only of mothers but also of fathers and, fundamentally, of
Caring for the ethical ideal 151
every human being within every dimension of the human condition. To be cared for,
to be the recipient of the complete and single-minded attention of another, simply
because of our need for such attention, is to be initiated into and invested in the
moral life. In this way, caring is not just one important or even essential element in
the moral life, a complement to a commitment to justice, but indeed the very source
of all moral striving and ideals.
I hasten to add, as Noddings herself would, that she is no gender essentialist
(2002b, p. 103). She pleads agnosticism on the question of whether women are by
nature more inclined to caring. She simply observes that throughout history and
across cultures, women have been and are the primary care givers. Because caring
has been associated with second-class citizenship that hardly means that caring
should continue to be devalued as women seek equal partnership with men. Quite
the opposite is actually the case. Authentic human liberation and social justice,
Noddings argues, can only be achieved by caring people in caring communities.
Caring as engrossment and motivational displacement
But what does it mean to care for another person, whether a child, a spouse, a
friend, a neighbour or colleague or a stranger? Noddings often quotes the French
philosopher Simone Weil, who would have us be radically attentive to one another,
and who asserts that a primary question should guide our relations with others, if
those relations would be moral: ‘ “What are you going through?” ’ (Noddings, 1992,
p. 15; 1995, p. 67; 2002a, p. 14; 2002b, p.17) Like a mother responding to the cry
of her infant, we must receive the situation of the other as if it were our own. To do
so requires emptying ourselves of attention to our own situation, at least for the
moment, so as to make room to take in the existential condition of the other. For
the moment, and whatever our situation, her need becomes our need. Noddings has
her own vocabulary for this essential characteristic of the caring relationship. A
caring attention, receptivity, sympathy or disposability leads to engrossment, the
other’s situation taking over my consciousness, if only temporarily, which in turn
leads to motivational displacement, as I join with the other in trying to respond to her
needs. It is at this point that rationality, evaluation, judgement, something like
Aristotle’s phronesis, enters the picture. Concerted thinking, both with and on behalf
of the other, will often be necessary if the caring response is to be completed
effectively.
Asymmetrical reciprocity as moral interdependence
But caring is not just a one-way proposition. For every moment of engrossment and
motivational displacement on the part of the would-be carer, there must be a
reciprocal reception of that care by the intended cared-for. Because the self is a
relation, all acts of caring, however asymmetrical, are always characterized by both
give and take. The mother offers her breast to the crying infant, who receives it,
ceases crying and satisfies its hunger. The teacher suggests a new approach to a
152
R. Bergman
math problem to a frustrated student, who receives, entertains and applies this new
perspective or idea until the problem is solved. The need is met, the caring offered
by the carer is completed in the cared-for, the caring relationship is established,
maintained or enhanced.
In such seemingly simple and everyday acts of caring, much is a stake besides the
immediate need being addressed. The carer’s sense of herself as a caring person is
at stake. The cared-for’s sense of trust in the world as a safe and reliable place and
of herself as a centre of value worthy to be cared for, is at stake. In this way the
caring self, the ethical self, the ethical ideal, is made possible, established, maintained or enhanced. In the single act of giving and receiving care, the self of each
person is confirmed. One’s caring is worthy, one is worthy of care. This point is
crucial to Noddings’s entire argument: one learns not only how to care by being
cared for, one learns that one must care if the self that has been confirmed by
receiving care is to be sustained. Noddings insists that any single moment of care
given and received is always asymmetrical, whatever form the relationship takes in
other moments, and however much it is always reciprocal. Caring offered needs to be
received. Indeed, ‘acknowledgement of the contribution of recipients of care may be
the very heart of the care theory. It recognizes moral interdependence’ (Noddings,
2002b, p. 87–88). For this reason, ‘learning to be cared for is the first step in moral
education’ (2002a, p. 24).
How do moral obligation and motivation arise?
But what happens when caring is not received or when the impulse to care does not
arise spontaneously or is potentially thwarted by difficult circumstances or feelings?
What happens when natural caring is not enough?
From natural to ethical caring
Although Noddings prefers Hume’s focus on the moral sentiments to Kant’s narrow
focus on affectless duty, she does fully acknowledge the reality of moral obligation,
what she calls the ‘I must’. When natural caring is not enough, we must be able to
summon up ethical caring. Noddings offers an alternative to Kant’s categorical
imperative: ‘Always act so as to establish, maintain, or enhance caring relations’
(1995, p. 188). But why would one do so when caring does not come naturally,
spontaneously, or without resistance?
Why … do we recognize an obligation to care? … In the ethic of care we accept our
obligation because we value the relatedness of natural caring … When we care, we must
employ reasoning to decide what to do and how best to do it … But reason is not what
motivates us. It is feeling with and for the other that motivates us in natural caring. In
ethical caring, this feeling is subdued, and so it must be augmented by a feeling for our
own ethical selves. (Noddings, 2002b, p. 14)
And to have selves adequate to the challenge of ethical caring, we must care for our
Caring for the ethical ideal 153
own and one another’s ethical ideals. An education that would be moral must
‘nurture the ethical ideals of those with whom … [educators, inside and outside
formal schooling] … come in contact’ (Noddings, 1984a, p.49). Before outlining
and exemplifying Noddings’s views on how education can be moral, we need to pay
a little more attention to her notion of the relational self and the ethical ideal.
The ethical self: a relation under construction
‘Selves are not born’ (Noddings, 2002a, p. 98) but rather are under continual
construction through encounters of all kinds, the effects these encounters produce
and reflective evaluation of these effects. Noddings notes that ‘some philosophers
call these ratings second-order evaluations … I think whether I should feel the way
I do about various encounters. The self at previous moments becomes another
object of encounter, affect, and evaluation. I approve of certain ways of being in the
world and reject others’ (2002a, p. 99). The measure of such second-order evaluations is the ideal that is the caring self, just as the measure of first-order evaluation
of affects is the ideal of the caring response. The relation between affect and self,
between first- and second-order evaluations, is incremental and as part to whole: ‘As
we try to educate the caring response in every subject that we teach and in a myriad
of everyday activities, we contribute to the construction of an ethical ideal. At the
core of this ideal is a habitual self that is caring’ (Noddings, 2002a, p. 215).
Noddings suggests that ‘it might be useful to think of [this] self as a sort of script by
which the organism directs and interprets its encounters’ (2002a, p. 100; emphasis
added). Elsewhere, she speaks of moral duty as arising ‘from faithfulness to an ideal
picture of ourselves’ (1995, p. 187; emphasis added). But because the self is a
relation and because we have many relationships, ‘the organism is not the sole
“author” of the script-like self: other selves contribute to its construction’ (Noddings, 2002a, p. 100). In a very real sense, there is no one ‘true self’ apart from the
ideal self that is always under construction through multiple authorship.
However, ‘this does not cast us into relativism, because the ideal contains at its
heart a component that is universal: Maintenance of the caring relation’ (Noddings,
1984a, p. 85). But ‘what if the cared-for turns rotten—must be judged evil—in light
of the ethic of caring?’ A caring person ‘will not collaborate with evil wherever it
occurs’ (1984a, p. 111), even if the evil-doer is intimate to her. The one-caring must
not abandon caring as an ideal and as the basis of their relationship when it has been
abandoned in practice by the one cared-for. But ‘does this mean that the one-caring
does, after all, place principle above specific persons?’ Noddings ‘do[es] not think
that conclusion is justified’ (1984a, p. 111). For the ‘commitment to receive the
other, to preserve the possibility of caring, is unshakeable’ (1984a, p. 111–112),
precisely in regard to the specific person who has turned ‘rotten’. One must continue
to offer to care even when the care is refused. For such reasons, Noddings confesses
that ‘when we understand how enormously complex the relational self is, we tremble
at the possibilities’ (2002a, p. 142). Nevertheless, Noddings can affirm, in the
familiar language of Walt Whitman:
154
R. Bergman
Do I contradict myself?
Very well then I contradict myself;
I am large, I contain multitudes. (Quoted in 2002a, p. 113)
The goal is not the ‘true self’ as an autonomy to be discovered and maintained, nor
a unified self without Whitman-like capaciousness, nor yet a merely consistent or
coherent self, since that could mean stagnation. Noddings’s goal for education as for
moral life would seem to be growth, as articulated in Dewey’s Experience and
education (1938), but going beyond Dewey, a growth toward not only the ethical
ideal of the habitually socially intelligent response, but toward a response that
enhances the caring self.2
Having responded to the questions—What is Noddings’s vision of the moral life?
And how do moral obligation and motivation arise? —we can now turn to our third
and final question.
How can education contribute to the moral life of students?
I will focus on what Noddings has to say about moral education per se and not on
how a caring orientation would remake all education so that it would be moral. In
Caring, Noddings describes ‘three great means of nurturing the ethical ideal’ (1984a,
p. 182): dialogue, practice and confirmation. In later books, she adds modelling as
a fourth component (1992, p. 22; 1995, p. 190; 2002a, p. 287). I will give a brief
description and example of each.
Modelling
Modelling is important to education generally and to many visions of moral
education specifically, but it is ‘especially important’ to an education based on care.
‘We have to show in our own behavior what it means to care. Thus we do not merely
tell [our students] to care and give them texts to read on the subject; we demonstrate
our caring in our relations with them’ (Noddings, 1995, p. 190). Modelling in the
moral domain may be especially powerful ‘because its very authenticity is morally
significant’ (2002a, p. 287). As a negative example, Noddings observes that ‘professors of education and school administrators cannot be sarcastic and dictatorial with
teachers in the hope that coercion will make them care for students’ Such inauthenticity is also morally significant: ‘the likely outcome is that teachers will then turn
attention protectively to themselves rather than lovingly to their students’ (Noddings, 1992, p. 22). Ethical ideals will be diminished all around.
Dialogue
‘Dialogue is implied by the phenomenology of caring’ and in particular by the
‘criterion of engrossment’ (Noddings, 1995, p. 191). Dialogue allows us to receive
Caring for the ethical ideal 155
the other in a ‘common search for understanding, empathy, or appreciation’ and
‘builds up a substantial knowledge of one another that serves to guide our [caring]
responses’ (Noddings, 1992, p. 23). The subject matter amenable to dialogue in
school is vast. As one example, Noddings suggests that ‘care theorists agree with
Socrates that an education worthy of the name must help students to examine their
own lives and explore the great questions human beings have always asked’. But
Noddings ‘would not declare that the unexamined life is not worth living, but
would … raise questions: Is the unexamined life worth living? Should we decide this
for others? How do we feel about our own?’ (Noddings, 1995, p. 191; emphasis in
original). The modelling of an educator’s ethical ideals might become the object of
dialogue: ‘Is a tough teacher necessarily caring? … Is a permissive teacher caring?’
(1995, p. 190). Dialogue, in other words, is the way to model the caring ideal in
communication. As a stimulus to reflection, it is an especially powerful tool for
promoting the building of students’ ethical ideals. (Noddings, 2002a, p. 107)
Practice
In dialogue, the teacher models caring communication while the student practises it.
But the practice of caring should extend beyond one’s own classroom. ‘All students’,
according to Noddings, ‘should be involved in caring apprenticeships’ (Noddings,
1984a, p. 188), with the school custodian, groundskeeper, or kitchen staff, or as
classroom aides for younger children. Service opportunities should extend into the
community, in ‘hospitals, nursing homes, animal shelters, parks, [and] botanical
gardens’ (Noddings, 1984a, p. 187). Community service involves all ‘three great
means of nurturing the ethical ideal’ outlined so far: ‘Children need to participate in
caring with adult models who show them how to care, talk with them about the
difficulties and rewards of such work, and demonstrate in their own work that [the
ethical ideal of] caring is important’ (Noddings, 1995, p. 191; emphasis added).
Confirmation
Finally, ‘what we reveal to a student about himself as an ethical and intellectual
being has the power to nurture the ethical ideal or to destroy it … When we attribute
the best possible motive consonant with reality to the cared-for, we confirm him’
(Noddings, 1984a, p. 193). And ‘when we confirm someone, we identify a better
self and encourage its development’ but ‘we do not posit a single ideal for everyone
and then announce “high expectations for all” … Rather we recognise something
admirable, or at least acceptable, struggling to emerge in each person we encounter’
(Noddings, 1995, p. 192). An extension of this idea is found in Noddings’s approach to multicultural education. Students from different cultures should be
encouraged to engage in dialogue and ‘coexploration’ that would lead to ‘a recognition that the virtues we admire can be found in other ways of life, and that the evils
we deplore can be found in ours as well as those of others’ (Noddings, 1995,
p. 193).
156
R. Bergman
Summary
In the four great means of nurturing the ethical ideal—modelling, dialogue, practice
and confirmation—the best self of the educator seeks a caring relationship with the
best self of the student. That means responding to one’s own sense of ‘I must’ by
asking, ‘what are you going through?’ which requires receptivity and leads to
engrossment, motivational displacement, and the most competent reasoning toward
as adequate a response as possible. The educator recognizes the powerful role he or
she plays as one of the most influential of the ‘authors’ of the script that is the
student’s ethical self. Although all our selves are under continuing construction, a
teacher may experience a satisfying completion when he sees his caring received with
care, when he sees a student growing in care for others and her own ethical ideals.
Such is the goal of moral education to which Nel Noddings directs us.
Noddings’s critique of character education3
But as Noddings herself acknowledges, it is not the theme of caring and the
concomitant educational components of modelling, dialogue, practice and
confirmation, as she articulates them, that are in the ascendancy in education.
Rather, ‘character education today dominates the field of practice in moral education’ (Noddings, 2002b, p. xiii). Others have sometimes characterized the ethics
of caring as a variant of virtue ethics. Caring education, then, might be seen as a
variant of character education—but not by Noddings, at least not without considerable qualification.
Convergence
Just as she describes caring as an ethics of relation as distinguished from an ethics
of individual virtue, so does Noddings differentiate caring education from character
education, despite the two having much in common (Noddings, 2002b, p. xiii). The
convergence is in four broad areas. Firstly and most generally, both character and
care proponents agree that moral education should be directed at producing better
people and not just better principles or reasoning. Nonetheless, and secondly, both
care and character educators do value moral reasoning, the former perhaps more so,
although neither group believes moral principles themselves provide sufficient motivation for moral action. Thirdly, care theorists certainly respect the virtues,
although they differ with character theorists on how they are best taught (Noddings,
2002b, p.1). Finally, Noddings observes that unlike moral philosophers since Kant
who have tended ‘to restrict the moral domain to considerations of our duties and
obligations to others’ but ‘like the ancient Greeks, character educators and care
theorists are concerned with the broader question, “How shall we live?” For both
camps, ‘the healthy development of oneself is thus included in a full discussion of
moral life’ (Noddings, 2002b, pp. 1–2).
Caring for the ethical ideal 157
Divergence
The fundamental difference, on the other hand, is that care ethics, which Noddings
distinguishes from virtue ethics in the Aristotelian tradition, is ‘relation-centered
rather than agent-centered, and … is more concerned with the caring relation than
with caring as a virtue’ (Noddings, 2002b, p. 2). This general difference is played
out in four more specific differences. Firstly, care educators, says Noddings, are
‘wary of trying to inculcate virtues directly’ but rather ‘are far more concerned to
concentrate on establishing conditions [through modelling, dialogue, practice, and
confirmation] that will call forth the best in students, that will make being good both
possible and desirable’ (Noddings, 2002b, p. 2). Secondly, the curriculum of moral
education for care educators is not defined by one or another list of free-floating
virtues as it seems to be for some character educators, since for us, says Noddings,
‘virtues are defined situationally and relationally’ (Noddings, 2002b, p. 2). Again,
the emphasis is on conditions and context. Thirdly, ‘care theorists put far greater
emphasis on the “social” virtues [or moral sentiments] as described by David
Hume.’ (Noddings, 2002b, p. 2). Thus included in Noddings’s own non-definitive
list of virtues would be, for example, congeniality, emotional sensitivity and good
manners. Finally, while both types of educators make extensive use of stories,
teachers of care betray a sympathy for the cognitive-developmentalists in the
Kohlberg tradition by utilizing narratives to problematize ethical decisions, as well as
to arouse Humean sympathies, while character educators would be more likely to
use stories that portray inspirational heroes, thereby hoping to inculcate those same
virtues in their students (Noddings, 2002b, p. 2).4
Context and community
The basic problem with character education as direct inculcation, according to
Noddings, is that it decontextualizes the virtues. It abstracts the virtues from the
relationships and concerns of the students. It assumes that the virtues can be taught
apart from caring relations between teachers and students.5 Noddings assumes, on
the other hand, that good parents do indeed teach the virtues effectively, but only
because they do so in context, when the virtue of the virtue, one might say, is
existentially real at that moment, and when the virtues have been modelled and
practised in dialogue and confirmation in an established caring relation. Caring is
the foundation on which the virtues are built. That is as true in the classroom as it
is in the home. But we do not care in order to teach the virtues; we become virtuous
in order to care and while caring.
Noddings explores at least eight other weaknesses of character education (2002b,
pp. 3–8). These critiques do not necessarily arise specifically from a care perspective
nor are they unique to Noddings. For that reason and in the interest of space, I will
pass over all but one. The critique that I will take up—that character education is
overly and uncritically dependent on community—will set the context for the final
section of this paper, on Noddings’s analysis of moral evil.
158
R. Bergman
A major feature of character education, according to Noddings, is its dependence
on a strong community with a consensus on core values. This raises several issues.
For a school sponsored by a religious community, for example, this may be
assumed. But what about a school where no such consensus exists? Whose values
and which virtues are to be taught? Conversely, as Noddings observes, a strong
community is not necessarily a good one. Noddings reminds us that ‘fascist and
totalitarian states have been especially enthusiastic about character education’.
Moralistic indoctrination is moral mis-education. ‘It is a major problem for character educators … to show that their approach is not completely dictated by a particular tradition and that they can find a way to correct a tradition that has gone wrong’
(Noddings, 2002b, p. 5).
What is needed, claims Noddings, are ‘forms of community based on the primacy
of the other … in such communities the virtues to be prized will be relational rather
than personal … [;] trust, good cheer, equality, peace, and compatibility may be
more important … than … courage, honesty, and industry’ (Noddings, 2002b,
p. 67). She suggests that ‘communitarian liberalism’ or ‘liberal communitarianism’
may name the philosophical hybrid needed, in which both individual freedom and
the common good are valued. Noddings, of course, believes that an education
founded on care is more compatible with such a vision than is an education founded
exclusively on character. Care education in this context turns out to be something
of a hybrid itself, although it is not only that. As Noddings puts it, ‘like cognitivists,
we [care educators] would subject all values to careful, critical scrutiny, and, like
character educators, we would insist that the effects of our choices on our communities and the effects of our communities on our choices be taken into account’
(Noddings, 2002b, p. 23).
In her book Women and evil (1989), Noddings demonstrates how deeply a care
educator may engage in scrutiny of established values and traditions. In the space
remaining, I want to highlight some of this analysis, especially as it relates to moral
education. The key is the idea of ‘the other’.
Noddings’s analysis of moral evil and its implications for education
Critiquing the tradition
A primary portion of Women and evil is devoted to a feminist deconstruction of
traditional Western theodicy, the theology of evil, whose purpose has been to ‘justify
the ways of God to men’ (Milton, 1935 edn., p. 9) Key ideas from that discussion
are summarized in Educating moral people (Noddings, 2002b). Noddings believes
that tradition misnames evil in four ways. Firstly: earth, body, woman and nature are
devalued over against heaven, mind, man and spirit. Secondly: the infliction of
suffering is legitimated. Thirdly: evil is projected onto the other as enemy. And
lastly: the capacity for evil in our own shadow side is neglected (Noddings, 2002b,
pp. 105–106). This critical analysis leads to a constructive agenda: evil must be
redefined from a feminist, caring perspective (Noddings, 2002b, p. 106). What is
Caring for the ethical ideal 159
needed is a new morality of evil, and a concomitant moral education, that moves
beyond traditional dualisms and male/female stereotypes. Three elements will be
primary. Firstly, a morality of evil will include caring for one’s own otherness or
capacity for evil. Secondly, ethics will be recast as caring for ‘the other’. And thirdly,
as alluded to in the previous section, community will be redefined around the
primacy of the other, as inclusive. The other—as me, as not-me, and as not-us—will
be reclaimed, will be owned. Self-knowledge will provide the foundation for resistance to political manipulation that would demonize the enemy.
As Noddings contends, ‘what we require … is a morality of evil—a carefully
thought out plan by which to manage the evil in ourselves, in others, and in whatever
deities we posit’ (Noddings, 1989, p. 1). Noddings’s critique of Western theodicy
might be summarized as follows: if God can be justified in the face of evil, then evil
can be justified in the name of God. Better to abandon theodicy in favour of a
morality of evil which promises not to justify evil but to acknowledge and thereby
manage it. Better to posit a fallible God—‘Jung [in his Answer to job] … suggests that
the Christian view of God as all-good needs to be revised to incorporate an evil side
of the deity’ (Noddings, 2002b, p. 115)—and embrace a tragic sense of life. Better
to confirm our desire for good while acknowledging our capacity for evil than to
worship an omnibenevolent God who nonetheless requires the punishment of
sinners. Contrary to orthodox Christian doctrine, Noddings believes this may be an
either/or proposition. If we acknowledge a dark side in God, we are better able to
acknowledge a dark side in ourselves. And conversely, failure to posit a fallible God
may blind us to our own capacity for evil.
Renaming evil
But how would Noddings rename evil? Most fundamentally, as ‘a real presence … Just as disease is real and not just the illusion or absence of health’
(Noddings, 1989, p. 229). Furthermore, ‘evil is neither entirely out-there nor
entirely in-here; it is an interactive phenomenon that requires acceptance, understanding, and steady control rather than great attempts to overcome it once and for
all’ (Noddings, 1989, p. 210). More concretely, evil and moral evil are renamed in
three ways. Firstly, as ‘pain and the infliction of pain, [second, as] separation and the
neglect of relation, and [third, as] helplessness and the mystification that sustains it’
(Noddings, 1989, p. 103). These are precisely the conditions that the mother seeks
to avoid or counter by caring for her child (Noddings, 1989, p. 116). Conversely,
‘when one intentionally rejects the impulse to care and deliberately turns her back
on the ethical, she is evil, an